Science has long
advanced in part due to its rejection of religion as it uncovered information
inconvenient for believers and their institutions
Mar 14, 2014 |By
Mitchell Stephens
Science’s
contributions to the spread of disbelief is the least controversial segment of
the virtuous cycle for which I am arguing in seventeenth-century Europe. For
science’s methods are clearly troublesome for religion. The devout, to begin
with, are not wont to view their precepts merely as propositions to be controverted
or confirmed. The orthodox, as a rule, are used to arguments being settled by
authority, not experiment. The hope belief offers does not always stand up well
to observation and experience: life sometimes works out okay; sometimes it
doesn’t. Faith, particularly of the “certain-because-impossible” variety, and
reason have long been tussling. Miracles are notoriously miserly with evidence.
Revelation does not lend itself to experimental verification. And the mystical,
by its nature, fails to produce facts.
When
it is employed, the scientific method, consequently, has a way of uncovering
information that is inconvenient for religion. Conflicts are inevitable with
ancient holy books—most of which do end up proclaiming something or other on
“how” the earth works or “heaven goes.” Scientists in these centuries diverged
from Scripture at their peril. Galileo learned that. But in the end the greater
cost would be borne by the holy books. Catholic leaders did indeed have reason
to fear that, in taking Copernicus’ theory seriously, Galileo might encourage
people to take the Bible less seriously.
The
discovery of fossils of sea animals far from the sea seemed to some scientists
to provide a needed boost to the credibility of the flood story. “From all
this,” one scientist told the Royal Society at the start of the eighteenth
century, “it sufficiently appears, that there was a time when the water
overflowed all our earth, which could be none but the Noachian deluge.” One of
the seventeenth century’s great fossil collectors and naturalists, John Ray,
thought the matter out a little more deeply, however, and noted that a quick
flood should have deposed sea animals evenly over the earth, which was not how
fossils were distributed. Ray also observed that some of those fossilized sea
animals no longer exist. Shouldn’t they have been saved with Noah on the ark?
And
with science continuing to pick up speed, new observations kept arriving. The
British scientist Edmond Halley undertook some calculations in 1694:
The Rain of forty Days and Nights will be found to be a very small Part of the Cause of such a Deluge, for supposing it to rain all over the Globe as much in each Day, as it is now found to do in one of the rainiest Counties of England in the whole Year, viz. about forty Inches of Water per Diem, forty such Days could cover the whole Earth with but about twenty two Fathom Water, which would only drown the low Lands next the Sea.
The Rain of forty Days and Nights will be found to be a very small Part of the Cause of such a Deluge, for supposing it to rain all over the Globe as much in each Day, as it is now found to do in one of the rainiest Counties of England in the whole Year, viz. about forty Inches of Water per Diem, forty such Days could cover the whole Earth with but about twenty two Fathom Water, which would only drown the low Lands next the Sea.
Halley
did have to abjure. Acting on the advice of “a person whose judgment I have
great cause to respect,” he hastily retreated from his incautious analysis.
However, the doubts being raised about holy writ by scientifically inclined
minds were not so easily eased. John Keill, a scientist with a strong
religious bent, saw the danger: “These contrivers of Deluges have furnished the
Atheist with an argument which . . . is not so easily answer’d as their
theories are made,” Keill concedes.
Religion
is resilient, no doubt about that. When discussions in sacred texts become
difficult to defend as historical they are defended as metaphorical. Still,
seventeenth-century science was increasingly placing religion on the defensive.
When biblical tales such as that of Noah are shown to have been unlikely, that
makes it a little harder to subscribe to the truth of the Bible and a little
easier to dismiss it.
In
1623, Marin Mersenne, a monk who was at the center of a lively and productive
intellectual correspondence, insisted that Paris alone harbored 50,000
atheists. In 1652, the English physician and scientist Walter Charleton
wrote that his country “has of late produced . . . more swarms of atheistical
monsters . . . than any age, than any nation has been infested withal.” Both
likely were exaggerating or mislabeling attenuated Christianity as atheism.
Europe’s infestation of true, there-is-no-God “atheistical monsters” was
probably still rather small.
But
disbelief was, indeed, growing. And the science in which both Mersenne, an
important correspondent of Galileo’s, and Charleton were participating was
taking the lead in that questioning: Did the sun really stop in the sky for
Joshua? Was the entire earth actually flooded? If the mathematics of gravity
can explain movements of the planets, what need is there for an omnipotent
Being?
Scientists
can, of course, be religious. With rare exceptions (Galileo and
Halley possibly among them), the men who made the Scientific Revolution appear
to have sensed God behind what they were learning of the natural world. Their
increasingly diligent observations, their telescopes and their microscopes
enabled them to see what humans had never before seen. Their first reaction was
awe, and they understood awe as a religious emotion: “'Tis the contemplation of
the wonderful order, law and power of that we call nature,” writes Robert
Hooke, inventor of the microscope, “that does most magnify the beauty and
excellency of the divine providence, which has so disposed, ordered, adapted
and empowered each part so to operate as to produce the wonderful effects which
we see.”
The
logic of these awe-struck early scientists sometimes appears to have flagged,
as the historian Richard S. Westfall has noted: The “beauty and excellency” of
the universe are used to prove that there is a God, and He is good. And if we
see things that are ugly and unpleasant—such as “mice, cockroaches or snakes”?
Well, they simply “serve,” as Walter Charleton put it, “as a foil to set off
beauty.” How do we know that? Because, in essence, there is a God and He is
good.
A
similarly circular path leads to the conclusion that, in the words of that
proponent of experimentation Francis Bacon, “the world was made for man.” This
happy fact is demonstrated by the world’s multitudes of helpful touches,
including, according to one of these scientists, the horse’s ear, which
conveniently turns backward to better hear commands. Thus we comprehend God’s
plan. And if we happen to see some things that don’t appear to be doing a lot
for humankind—distant heavenly bodies, for example, or the aforementioned snakes—well,
that’s just a sign that we can never fully comprehend God’s plan.
Isaac
Newton, the greatest of these “natural philosophers,” shared the awe felt by
his contemporaries and drew similar conclusions from it. (There appears to have
been a fair amount of feigning religious belief in the seventeenth century, but
it seems unlikely that Newton’s expressions of faith could be explained that
way since they appear in numerous private as well as public writings.) Indeed,
he added the following line to the second edition of his monumental Philosophiæ
Naturalis Principia Mathematica: “This most elegant system of the sun, planets,
and comets could not have arisen without the design and dominion of an
intelligent and powerful being.” Some scientists at the time found
evidence of this “design” in the complexity of the universe; Newton, having
worked out his astoundingly powerful means for understanding the universe,
marveled, instead, at “the simplicity in all the works of the Creator.”
Yet
Newton and these other seventeenth-century scientists generally managed to keep
their awe from interfering with their investigations. The first edition of
Newton’s Principia, published in 1687, did not contain any discussion of “an
intelligent and powerful being.” It does not contain any discussion of theology
whatsoever. It was only after his book was criticized by Gottfried
Leibniz and others for impiety—for presenting space, gravity and the universe
in a way that appeared not to support an orthodox conception of God—that Newton
added a section discussing God’s role. Newton believed, but he had
initially managed to produce a mathematical understanding of motion, which
merely made intelligible the workings of the entire cosmos, without any overt
reference to that belief.
The
first edition of Newton’s book, with God conspicuously absent, helps form,
then, another segment of the virtuous cycle created by science and disbelief
(“atheism” would be too strong a word here) in seventeenth-century Europe. The
argument is that if Newton had dwelt in his book on God’s role, he might not
have done such a magnificent job of working out gravity’s role. If he were more
fearful of challenging understandings of God, if he were more content with
ceding responsibility to the whims of God, if he thought human reason could
never comprehend God’s Creation, Newton might not have been able to outline so
persuasively a physics and mathematics that manage to function so impressively
on their own.
Isaac
Newton was not above dabbling in the occult. He spent decades
experimenting with alchemy—making use of mystical sources and hoping to come
upon long-lost mystical secrets. The man who devised calculus,
understood inertia and quantified gravity also seemed obsessed (a word that
often comes to mind with Newton) with uncovering hidden secrets in the Bible,
which included, he suspected, a chronology of the past and the future.
Newton
was, in other words, ready to use religion in his immense and unceasing efforts
to figure things out. But he was less ready to allow religion to interfere with
those efforts. “It is the temper of the hot and superstitious part of mankind
in matters of religion ever to be fond of mysteries,” Newton writes, “and for
that reason to like best what they understand least.”
“The
progress of religion is defined,” writes the early-twentieth-century
philosopher Alfred North Whitehead, “by the denunciation of gods.”
Gods become fewer in number until there is only one—or a Father, Son and Holy
Ghost adding up to one. And the qualities of the lonely God that is left are
also denounced. He loses His home: God is no longer to be found inside a temple
or even, after airplanes, enthroned atop a cloud. He loses His physical form:
His beard, His voice, perhaps His body or even His gender. He is neither seen
nor heard in public. He grows wispier, more abstract.
Newton,
the scientist, probably was responsible for subtracting—denouncing—among the
most important of God’s qualities: his daily responsibility for the workings of
the heavens. And in his private scribblings on religion, Newton engaged in a
fair number of additional denunciations, too.
This
mathematician, who taught at Cambridge’s Trinity College, was, for example,
offended by the odd arithmetic of the Trinity—insisted upon by Anglicans as
well as Catholics. He inclined, in his private writings, toward a view of Jesus
as human rather than as one of three parts of one God. In addition,
this physicist was suspicious, as was Spinoza, of the idea that miracles “are
the works of God” rather than just rare and poorly understood phenomena. Like
Spinoza, Newton, when writing for himself, also had no use for a corporeal view
of God. Indeed, Newton—when not looking for hidden predictions, at
least—was partial to Spinoza’s reading of the Bible as a human document.
In
the historian Richard S. Westfall’s view, Newton was a “religious
rationalist.” He was looking for a stripped-down version of
religion: one compatible with his physics. He was also looking for the
principle that all religions have in common: “the law of righteousness and
charity,” he called it. A religious rationalist, however, is not an easy thing
to be.
To
maintain a rational view of “the Author of the system” it would be necessary,
for example, to resolve the contradictions that seem inherent in most
conceptions of God. There is, for example, that old conundrum about
omnipotence—given a twenty-first-century formulation on The Simpsons: “Could
Jesus microwave a burrito so hot that He Himself could not eat it?”
There is also Carneades’ argument, presented in chapter 2, that a being without
flaws or weaknesses couldn’t exhibit virtues. One question Newton and his
contemporaries certainly struggled with was what role a Perfect Being would
have after a presumably perfect Creation. Wouldn’t He be redundant
post-Genesis—after functioning as the First Cause? Wouldn’t Jehovah end up
resembling one of the Epicurean gods—left with no responsibility but to enjoy
Himself?
A
“religious rationalist” would also somehow have to get right the relationship between
the natural and the supernatural: what status would natural laws have if a
Being exists who is outside of them and violates them at least for the
Creation? It would be necessary, too, to square science’s methods with any sort
of reliance upon religious authority, including that Bible whose secrets Newton
was so interested in revealing. In addition, to be a “religious rationalist,”
in Newton’s sense, would require precipitating “righteousness and charity” out
of holy texts that do not always seem to embody them and out of a universe that
does not always seem to display them.
These
tasks may have been beyond the abilities of even this most able of men. Newton
wrote out his private treatises on religion—and then rewrote them and rewrote
them again. One appeared in at least five versions. As an old man, the Isaac
Newton who had gotten the physics of the heavens right was still trying to get
this rational view of Christianity right.
But
by then Newton had denounced enough to leave a rather hazy, unobtrusive God. In
Newton’s understanding, and that of many of his scientifically inclined
contemporaries, God was losing not only eyes, a nose, bluster and his two other
manifestations, but the inclination to fiddle with natural laws.
So
although he was a believer, Newton and his contemporaries help demonstrate what
disbelief—or, in his case, limited belief—can contribute to science. His
rejection of some of the more mystical and intrusive conceptions of God was
probably necessary in order to give the sun and the planets leave to abide by
equations. Newton’s physics, the point is, benefited from the rejection of some
religious belief.
Science
usually does. Its progress, we might say, is “defined” by the diminution of
God. Science requires some separation from church. This was, after Galileo,
becoming available in Europe in the seventeenth century. Hobbes and
Spinoza—however wary they may have been about speaking too “boldly”—helped. And
the tendency of scientists—Newton among them—to push aside assumptions they
considered irrational or unhelpful certainly helped. Newton’s ability to leave
God entirely out of the first edition of Principia Mathematica greatly helped.
A
distinguished nineteenth-century atheist, Charles Bradlaugh, deserves the honor
of making this point: “It is certainly a clear gain to astronomical science,”
Bradlaugh writes in an essay, “that the church which tried to compel Galileo to
unsay the truth has been overborne by the growing unbelief of the age, even
though our little children are yet taught that Joshua made the sun . . . stand
still.”
No comments:
Post a Comment